|
|
|
|
LEADER |
00000cam a2200000 i 4500 |
001 |
JSTOROA_on1101901816 |
003 |
OCoLC |
005 |
20231005004200.0 |
006 |
m o d |
007 |
cr cnu---unuuu |
008 |
190520t20191997nyu ob 001 0 eng d |
040 |
|
|
|a JSTOR
|b eng
|e rda
|e pn
|c JSTOR
|d UAB
|d STBDS
|d YDXIT
|d OCLCQ
|d OCLCO
|d DEGRU
|d SFB
|d OCLCQ
|d YDX
|d OCLCO
|d SGP
|d OCLCQ
|d YWS
|d OCLCQ
|
019 |
|
|
|a 1102734361
|
020 |
|
|
|a 9780823285235
|q (electronic book)
|
020 |
|
|
|a 0823285235
|q (electronic book)
|
020 |
|
|
|a 9780823284733
|q (electronic book)
|
020 |
|
|
|a 0823284735
|
029 |
1 |
|
|a AU@
|b 000065306319
|
029 |
1 |
|
|a AU@
|b 000074026674
|
035 |
|
|
|a (OCoLC)1101901816
|z (OCoLC)1102734361
|
037 |
|
|
|a 22573/ctvh3gztg
|b JSTOR
|
050 |
|
4 |
|a B945.P44
|b P6 2019
|
082 |
0 |
4 |
|a 191
|2 23
|
049 |
|
|
|a UAMI
|
100 |
1 |
|
|a Potter, Vincent G.,
|e author.
|
245 |
1 |
0 |
|a Charles S. Peirce on norms & ideals /
|c by Vincent G. Potter ; with a new introduction by Stanley M. Harrison.
|
246 |
3 |
|
|a Charles S. Peirce on norms and ideals
|
250 |
|
|
|a First Open Access edition.
|
264 |
|
1 |
|a New York :
|b Fordham University Press,
|c 2019.
|
264 |
|
4 |
|c ©1997
|
300 |
|
|
|a 1 online resource
|
336 |
|
|
|a text
|b txt
|2 rdacontent
|
337 |
|
|
|a computer
|b c
|2 rdamedia
|
338 |
|
|
|a online resource
|b cr
|2 rdacarrier
|
490 |
1 |
|
|a American philosophy series ;
|v no. 6
|
500 |
|
|
|a Originally published: [Amherst] : University of Massachusetts Press, 1967.
|
504 |
|
|
|a Includes bibliographical references (pages 215-220) and indexes.
|
505 |
0 |
|
|a pt. I. Pragmatism & the Normative Sciences -- pt. II. Synechism & Law -- pt. III. Tychism & Evolusion.
|
520 |
|
|
|a In Charles S. Peirce: On Norms and Ideals, Potter argues that Peirce's doctrine of the normative sciences is essential to his pragmatism. No part of Peirce's philosophy is bolder than his attempt to establish esthetics, ethics, and logic as the three normative sciences and to argue for the priority of esthetics among the trio. Logic, Potter cites, is normative because it governs thought and aims at truth; ethics is normative because it analyzes the ends to which thought should be directed; esthetics is normative and fundamental because it considers what it means to be an end or something good in itself. This study shows that Peirce took seriously the trinity of normative sciences and demonstrates that these categories apply both to the conduct of man and to the workings of the cosmos.
|
588 |
0 |
|
|a Online resource; title from digital title page (viewed on June 03, 2019).
|
590 |
|
|
|a JSTOR
|b Books at JSTOR Open Access
|
590 |
|
|
|a JSTOR
|b Books at JSTOR All Purchased
|
600 |
1 |
0 |
|a Peirce, Charles S.
|q (Charles Sanders),
|d 1839-1914.
|
600 |
1 |
7 |
|a Peirce, Charles S.
|q (Charles Sanders),
|d 1839-1914.
|2 fast
|0 (OCoLC)fst00033077
|
650 |
|
0 |
|a Norm (Philosophy)
|x History.
|
650 |
|
0 |
|a Ideals (Philosophy)
|x History.
|
650 |
|
6 |
|a Norme (Philosophie)
|x Histoire.
|
650 |
|
6 |
|a Idéaux (Philosophie)
|x Histoire.
|
650 |
|
7 |
|a PHILOSOPHY
|x Movements
|x Pragmatism.
|2 bisacsh
|
650 |
|
7 |
|a Ideals (Philosophy)
|2 fast
|0 (OCoLC)fst00966854
|
650 |
|
7 |
|a Norm (Philosophy)
|2 fast
|0 (OCoLC)fst01039115
|
655 |
|
0 |
|a Electronic books.
|
655 |
|
7 |
|a History.
|2 fast
|0 (OCoLC)fst01411628
|
776 |
0 |
8 |
|i Print version :
|z 9780823217090
|
830 |
|
0 |
|a American philosophy series ;
|v no. 6.
|
856 |
4 |
0 |
|u https://jstor.uam.elogim.com/stable/10.2307/j.ctvh4zg18
|z Texto completo
|
938 |
|
|
|a YBP Library Services
|b YANK
|n 17870618
|
938 |
|
|
|a De Gruyter
|b DEGR
|n 9780823285235
|
938 |
|
|
|a Oxford University Press USA
|b OUPR
|n EDZ0002046748
|
994 |
|
|
|a 92
|b IZTAP
|